I spent one morning at the JMMs this week in a session on the Introduction-To-Proofs course (aka the Bridge course). I enjoyed the session; it contained some good techniques to include, some good warnings of things to avoid, etc. Such a course always includes learning about proof by contradiction.
Now, I have a bit of a thing about proof by contradiction. It's not that it's invalid; it's that, at least in classical logic, you can always transform a proof by contradiction into a proof by contraposition; in any case, while I'm not a constructivist and think that intuitionistic logic is mostly a curiosity, it's nice to have a proof which provides an implicit algorithm, when such a thing exists.
So today on the train I was puzzling over a little bit of boolean-algebra arithmetic which Tom Jech uses in his exposition of forcing. (I'm supervising an undergrad who wants to learn forcing, and the boolean-valued-model approach is so much nicer than the poset-only approach.) I tried to prove it forwards six ways to Sunday, and nothing seemed to work. So, remembering what we all tell students in Bridge courses, I turned it around and tried to prove it by contradiction, and that took all of six lines. I still don't see a direct proof that's not an artificial translation of the contradiction/contraposition result; if you know one, put it in the comments!
Theorem: Recall that in boolean algebras, the implication operation v1⇒v2 is defined as v2∨¬v1. If x,y,z belong to a boolean algebra B and x∧y=x∧z, then x≤(y⇔z).
Proof: Suppose otherwise. Then we can find elements x,y,z in a boolean algebra B so that
x>y⇒z=x∧(z∨(¬y))
Now observe that
x∧(z∨(¬y))=(x∧z)∨(x∧¬y)=(x∧z)∨(x∧y)∨(x∧¬y)=(x∧z)∨x≥x
Overall, x>x, a contradiction.
Now, I have a bit of a thing about proof by contradiction. It's not that it's invalid; it's that, at least in classical logic, you can always transform a proof by contradiction into a proof by contraposition; in any case, while I'm not a constructivist and think that intuitionistic logic is mostly a curiosity, it's nice to have a proof which provides an implicit algorithm, when such a thing exists.
So today on the train I was puzzling over a little bit of boolean-algebra arithmetic which Tom Jech uses in his exposition of forcing. (I'm supervising an undergrad who wants to learn forcing, and the boolean-valued-model approach is so much nicer than the poset-only approach.) I tried to prove it forwards six ways to Sunday, and nothing seemed to work. So, remembering what we all tell students in Bridge courses, I turned it around and tried to prove it by contradiction, and that took all of six lines. I still don't see a direct proof that's not an artificial translation of the contradiction/contraposition result; if you know one, put it in the comments!
Theorem: Recall that in boolean algebras, the implication operation v1⇒v2 is defined as v2∨¬v1. If x,y,z belong to a boolean algebra B and x∧y=x∧z, then x≤(y⇔z).
Proof: Suppose otherwise. Then we can find elements x,y,z in a boolean algebra B so that
x>y⇒z=x∧(z∨(¬y))
Now observe that
x∧(z∨(¬y))=(x∧z)∨(x∧¬y)=(x∧z)∨(x∧y)∨(x∧¬y)=(x∧z)∨x≥x
Overall, x>x, a contradiction.
No comments:
Post a Comment